Comments on The Hero Within

herowithin

I have begun exploring Jungian archetypes and the role they play in stories.  I am currently rereading Christopher Booker’s The Seven Basic Plots: Why We Tell Stories, in which Jung and his ideas are mentioned several times.  But what really fascinates me is the analyses author Jeffrey Alan Schechter provides in his screenwriting book My Story Can Beat Up Your Story.  In this book, Schechter writes (Pg 39-40):

I am a huge fan of a book by Carol S. Pearson entitled The Hero Within, which explores the six archetypes that real-life people embody: the Innocent, the Orphan, the Magician, the Wanderer, the Martyr [or Altruist], and the Warrior. …

While discussing Ms. Pearson’s ideas with my good friend Gilbert Maclean Evans, he pointed out that in every film he could thing of the hero moved through four of the six archetypes from opening moment to final fade.  We looked at a bunch of movies and it was true.  Every movie, four archetypes.  And not only does the hero move through these four archetypes, he or she does so like the proverbial Swiss clock.

The four archetypes are: Orphan, Wanderer, Warrior, Martyr.  In every story, the hero moves through these archetypes.  In Act 1, he is an Orphan, spiritually if not literally, detached from family or a solid familial support base.  In Act 2, he begins as a Wanderer, exploring the world that the story’s catalyst brought about.  Half way through Act 2, he becomes a Warrior, fighting for something, again spiritually if not literally.  In Act 3, the hero learns to become a Martyr, trusting in a higher power to achieve what he’s after, unafraid of dying in the process.  (Sometimes the martyrdom beat is played out by a supporting character, providing the hero the necessary “push” to step into this role himself.)

We see this again and again in stories of all sorts.  There’s something about these archetypes and the process of journeying through them that really resonates with us.

So that’s why I’m exploring Jungian archetypes.  I’m interested to see if there are any deeper truths to be found in this area, especially in how they relate to storytelling.

So I started reading Pearson’s The Hero Within: Six Archetypes We Live By.  It seems to be meant as some sort of psychological self-help book, the idea being that if you can recognize these archetypes within yourself, it will help you understand yourself, solve problems in your life, and find inner strength.  For better or worse, I’m not really taking these self-help messages at face value, but perhaps a human’s love of stories is, on some level, driven by a sense of seeking guidance, not just entertainment.  But guidance in a way that is not as direct and perhaps as upsetting as “this is why you’re wrong about stuff,” thus allowing you to interpret and integrate a story’s message in a way that, for lack of better phrasing, “works for you.”

Anyway, some of this book seems downright ridiculous.  Listing the ways understanding these archetypes can help you, Pearson writes (Pg 29):

[Reason] Seven: Archetypal recognition can help you better understand others and how they see the world.

This seems a rather presumptuous claim, if not self-righteous, especially if it’s in regard to someone you’re in a disagreement with.  Reason eight is similar (Pg 30):

Eight: Understanding the archetypal basis for the ways in which people see the world cannot only make you smarter, but also help you see beyond the unconscious bias scholars and journalists often bring to their work.

So not only will you understand others better, you’ll see their unconscious biases!  This book seems to encourage readers to form delusions.

Pearson writes (Pg 30):

… if your boss criticizes you nonstop, that may be evidence of the Warrior’s worry that someone may let the team down.  He will stay on your case until he is satisfied that you are smart enough and tough enough to handle things on your own.  This can be particularly annoying if you are a woman or a man of color and the boss is male and white.  It will feel like racism or sexism (which to a lesser or greater degree it is).

Wha . . . what?? 

Anyway, I’m still curious to know what the author says about the archetypes, but I’m definitely not buying into these notions that they will help you understand other people.  That seems a rather dangerous thing to assume.

Ender’s World: Fresh Perspectives on the SF Classic Ender’s Game edited by Orson Scott Card

endersworld

Link: Ender’s World: Fresh Perspectives on the SF Classic Ender’s Game

Summary: A collection of fourteen diverse essays by a diverse group of contributors on Orson Scott Card’s famous book Ender’s Game.  Contributors include writer Eric James Stone, writer Mary Robinette Kowal, Burn Notice creator Matt Nix, among many others.  The essay topics are also quite varied, including philosophical observations, storytelling observations, and even military application observations.  Between each chapter, Card answers various questions about the making of Ender’s Game.  This isn’t a book of literary criticism, the sort of essays college dweebs might write for some boring class.  These are personal essays, the writers responding casually yet honestly about how the book affected them, about how some attribute of the book influenced their lives.

Thoughts: I very much enjoyed this book; I wish it were longer!  My favorite essays included “How it Should Have Ended” by Eric James Stone, “The Monster’s Heart” by John Brown, “The Cost of Breaking the Rules” by Mary Robinette Kowal, “A Teenless World” by Mette Ivie Harrison, “Ender on Leadership” by Colonel Tom Ruby, “Ender Wiggin, USMC” by John F. Schmitt, and “Ender’s Game: A Guide to Life” by Matt Nix.

A few short random comments on them:

The first three essays by Stone, Brown, and Kowal are, I think, great for writers.

In “How it Should Have Ended”, Stone writes on page 8:

One of the best pieces of advice I have received about writing characters is that you should figure out what a character desires most—and what the character fears most.  With that knowledge, you can craft a climax to a story that puts the desire and the fear into conflict.  By making the stakes as high as possible on a personal level, the climax of the story is more powerful.

Stone goes on to show how Card does this in Ender’s Game.  Very insightful for the aspiring writer.

In “The Monster’s Heart”, Brown writes on page 23:

For fiction to provide an experience then, all it needs to do is present the situational cues to us that will automatically trigger our appraisals and physiological responses. … despite the often-repeated eleventh writing commandment, “Show, don’t tell,” the truth of the matter is that a text never shows a reader anything except marks on a page … Movies and plays can show.  They can also provide raw auditory input.  But a book never *shows* us anything.  It’s *all* tell, tell, tell.  The trick is to tell in a way that allows the reader to imagine the situation with enough clarity and realism that the imagined situation triggers the response.

And of course he goes on to show how Card does this in Ender’s Game.  This is also very insightful for the aspiring writer.

You may have already heard some of Kowal’s writing observations in “The Cost of Breaking the Rules” from the podcast she co-hosts, Writing Excuses.  But there’s more here.  She makes some very interesting observations, ones I did not notice when I first read Ender’s Game.  Granted, it was before I became interested in polishing my writing craft and started paying attention to how authors do what they do.  Still, it’s fascinating to see how somebody’s writing can affect you in ways you don’t even notice.  Which must be why we can recognize when a story moves us, yet be incapable of recreating the experience with our own work, things like point-of-view, how it’s written and how it shifts, etc.  Anyway, yet another very insightful essay for the aspiring writer.

In a Q&A section between chapters, Card offers another great writing advice gem on pages 61-62:

Too many people think characterization is about finding an interesting backstory for the character, or inventing quirks and eccentricities and mannerisms.  Those are actually cheap tricks; it’s what you do to make characters without actually having to create them with any depth.

Instead, real characterization is figuring out who they are, what attitude and manner they present, in *each* of their significant relationships.  This is hard work!

What interested me in Harrison essay, “A Teenless World”, was the notion that teenagerhood is a modern concept.  While I’m not sure I agree with her theory that technology has caused this artificial extension of childhood (though there is certainly a correlation), her essay certainly resonated with me.  If you’ve read my other blog, you may know that I believe that “there’s no such thing as a teenager.”

“Ender on Leadership” and “Ender Wiggin, USMC” had some very interesting insights into how Ender’s Game affected military personnel.

One of them mentioned the idea that a good leader does not seek to maintain his status as leader.  He hires people who can get the job done, even if that means his own weaknesses will be pointed out.  A good leader recognizes his own weaknesses, fully admits to them, and seeks help to overcome them.  He does not try to hide them, thereby hiring only people who would not notice them or would pretend not to care about them and thereby not challenge the leader’s power.  Maintaining a leadership position for it’s own sake, for the sake of mere power over others, is useless.

The other essay talks about how war games (“TDGs”) were designed to help commanders make tough strategic choices on the battlefield.  Rather than designing games constricted by artificial rules (because in real combat, the “rules” are unknown), commanders come up with solutions to problem scenarios and their solutions are discussed and compared and critiqued.  The point is to help commanders learn how to think instead of trying to teach them specifically what to think.  (“In this situation, do this.  In that situation, do that.”)  These sorts of “games” are similar to games Ender is forced to play in Ender’s Game; open ended game meant to encourage strategic thinking.

Matt Nix’s article, “Ender’s Game: A Guide to Life”, most closely matched my own way of thinking after I first read Ender’s Game, and how my thinking evolved in the years after I continued to dwell on the issues brought up in Ender’s Game.  Issues such as how I relate to Ender personally and what his decisions and outlook affect my own.

For example, consider the role suffering plays in any story, particularly in Ender’s Game.  It’s something I’ve wondered about for a long while.  Why do we like to imagine being characters who suffer?  On page 276, Nix writes:

Suffering, by itself, is just suffering.  A guy throwing a script at you because the fax machine is broken isn’t *really* a lesson, any more than Ender’s torment at Bonzo’s hands was.  Lessons are only lessons if you choose to see them that way.  In some ways, wasn’t that really Ender’s greatest skill—his ability to learn from his torment?

Another lesson Nix writes about involves figuring out what matters.  If you want to “make it”, you’ll have to understand that what matters to other people is the bottom line, not how you feel about it.  But that doesn’t mean you shouldn’t care about your own feelings.  On page 278-279, Nix writes:

At the end of the day, you have to deliver the goods, and people don’t much care how you feel about it.

The ends *don’t* justify the means.  Nothing justifies anything.  There’s just what you do, and whether you can live with it.  It may be true that the only thing anyone *else* cares about is whether you won, but that doesn’t mean it’s the only thing that matters.

Overall, great collection of essays here.  I very much enjoyed this book and will probably be returning to read some of these essays again.  Great stuff.

The Logic of Scientific Discovery: Chapter 1, part 2

Link: The Logic of Scientific Discovery

Before continuing where I left off after Chapter 1, part 1, I wanted to quote another book.  The following quote is from Nassim Nicholas Taleb’s fantastic book, Fooled by Randomness: The Hidden Role of Chance in Life and in the Markets.  Taleb’s book deals with the “problem of induction” a great deal, so it’s only natural that the subject of Karl Popper comes up in the book.  Strangely, even though Popper is mentioned throughout Fooled by Randomness (and in Taleb’s other fantastic book, The Black Swan: Second Edition: The Impact of the Highly Improbable), I simply glossed over the name and did not become interested in Popper’s work until late last year.  Anyway, Taleb sums up Popper’s thoughts on the problem of induction more concisely than I can, so I thought he’d be worth quoting.  The following is from Fooled by Randomness, page 126:

Popper came up with a major answer to the problem of induction (to me he came up with the answer). … There are only two types of theories:

1. Theories that are known to be wrong, as they were tested and adequately rejected (he calls them falsified).

2. Theories that have not yet been known to be wrong, not falsified yet, but are exposed to be proved wrong.

Why is a theory never right?  Because we will never know if all the swans are white (Popper borrowed the Kantian idea of the flaws in our mechanisms of perception).  The testing mechanism may be faulty.  However, the statement that there is a black swan is possible to make.  A theory cannot be verified. … It can only be provisionally accepted.  A theory that falls outside of these two categories is not a theory.  A theory that does not present a set of conditions under which it would be considered wrong would be termed charlatanism—it would be impossible to reject otherwise.

On page 127, Taleb continues:

[Popper] refused to blindly accept the notion that knowledge can always increase with incremental information—which is the foundation of statistical inference.  It may in some instances, but we do not know which ones.

I think these are very important things to note, and it’s interesting that even today perhaps most people would not understand or accept these notions.  Anyway, this sums up the basic understanding with which I am approaching my reading of Popper.

And now, to finish Chapter 1.

Section 6: Falsifiability as a criterion for demarcation

In this section, I think Popper is establishing that the ability for a theory to be falsified is what distinguishes empirical statements from non-empirical statements.  In this sense, verification is impossible, as Taleb states in the quote above.

Section 7: The problem of ‘empirical basis’

Here, I think Popper is asking: How do our experiences relate to the statements we develop?  He is trying to deny the intuitive notion that experiencing something verifies anything but a useless tautological statement (such as “I experienced this!”).  Popper writes on page 21:

Perceptual experiences have often been regarded as providing a kind of justification for basic statements.  It was held that these statements are ‘based upon’ these experiences; that their truth becomes ‘manifest by inspection’ through these experiences; or that it is made ‘evident’ by these experiences, etc. … Yet it was also rightly felt that statements can be logically justified only be statements.

Popper continues on page 22:

Here too a solution can be found, I believe, if we clearly separate the psychological from the logical and methodological aspects of the problem.  We must distinguish between, on the one hand, our subjective experiences of our feelings of conviction, which can never justify any statement … and, on the other hand, the objective logical relations subsisting among the various systems of scientific statements, and within each of them.

That is, statements, and the logic behind their falsification and correction or abandonment, are separate from our experiences.  Related, sure, but not directly derived from them.  We experience something, create a statement, then “detach” ourselves from it, pushing it into the realm of “objective logical relations.”

Section 8: Scientific objectivity and subjective conviction

The main thing I get out of this section is that the idea of “conviction” counts for nothing scientifically.  It may still matter a great deal in a person’s decision making, but it doesn’t justify anything.  Hence the distinction between scientific objectivity and subjective conviction.

Conclusion

And that’s Chapter 1 of this book!  I’m not sure whether or not I will continue on to Chapter 2 just yet.  I may start reading a different nonfiction book instead.  This is for two reasons:

1. This book is still a bit heavy for me; it still takes quite a bit of time and focus for me to understand what Popper saying, and even when I think I do, I can’t be certain my understanding is correct.  (I can’t verify my understanding!)

2. I have completed, on paper, an algorithm that would, in theory, teach itself to play chess, which is why I was exploring Popper’s work in the first place.  I have yet to try my ideas; the algorithm is complicated and it will take some time to program.  And, of course, it probably won’t work, because something this ambitious could never work on a first try.  Anyway, trying to translate my messy notes into a programming language will be confusing enough without having to try to ponder what Karl Popper is saying.

The Logic of Scientific Discovery: Chapter 1, part 1

popperlosd

Link: The Logic of Scientific Discovery

I have started reading Karl Popper’s The Logic of Scientific Discovery.  As I mentioned on my other blog and in my short AI research journal, I seek to create Strong AI, and I think Popper’s work may have some useful insights.  (For the moment, I seek to create a system that can teach itself to play any rule-based game, such as chess.  Humans can do it, so there must be a way to program a computer to do it.)  I have already gained useful insights by reading the first 90 pages of Popper’s book Objective Knowledge, and certainly there is some overlap between that book and this.  But I have, for the moment, halted my reading of Objective Knowledge in favor of this volume.

Interestingly, when I Google information on Karl Popper, he seems to have some atheist followers, which I find strange.  From the what I’ve read so far (which admittedly isn’t much), he never says anything that should cast doubt on theism in and of itself.  Popper would very much disagree with Ayn Rand’s atheist epistemology, for example, or at least her attempt at forming one.  Perhaps this is part of the larger blindness among certain atheists who cannot understand how logic and science are not only compatible with belief in a deity, but dependent on it.  “If it has to do with science, then it must support my atheism, because science and God are incompatible ideas!” one might claim.  But I don’t have much else to say on this subject because it is boring, like arguing with a child who refuses to believe letters mean anything just because he can’t read, and so develops no system with which to recognize them.

What follows are just summaries of my understandings and thoughts on various sections.  I don’t claim to be an expert, so feel free to correct me if you think I understand Popper wrongly. I certainly admit I am not always sure what the man is trying to say. I am not a well-read philosophy student by any means, so many times his writings are a bit complicated for me.

Chapter 1: A survey of some problems

Section 1: The problem of induction

Popper gives a solution to the “problem” of induction.  (He discusses it in more depth in Objective Knowledge.)  A classic example of the problem of induction goes like this: I see a bunch of white swans.  I therefore think, “All swans are white!”  Later, I see a black swan.  My theory that all swans are white is obviously shown to be false.  So if I am creating knowledge from observations, how can I really know anything? (See the Wikipedia article on the subject for more detail.)  Popper’s solution (from what I can understand): When I say, “All swans are white!” I am creating a theory, based not only on my observations (certainly the observations have to fit my theory), but also on the belief that there is a grander truth to what I am observing.  I cannot say that I know all swans are white; I cannot generalize the color of all swans based only on those I have seen.  “All swans are white” was never really knowledge to begin with, so there is no problem when the theory is refuted.

Popper makes a distinction between “psychology of knowledge” and “logic of knowledge.”

From page 7:

I must first make a clear distinction between the psychology of knowledge which deals with empirical facts, and the logic of knowledge which is concerned only with logical relations.  For the belief in inductive logic is largely due to a confusion of psychological problems with epistemological ones.

Section 2: Elimination of psychologism

As Popper says on page 7:

The question of how it happens that a new idea occurs to a man … may be of great interest to empirical psychology; but it is irrelevant to the logical analysis of scientific knowledge.

That is, the question of how one creates a theory and how one corrects a refuted theory (which I attempted to answer in my aforementioned journal) are two different subjects, and how one creates a theory is of far less interest here.

On page 8, Popper writes:

… my view on the matter … is that there is no such thing as a logical method of having new ideas, or a logical reconstruction of this process.

I both agree and disagree with Popper here, and I wish he were alive so I could ask him to elaborate on what exactly he means here.  (Though if he were alive, I’m sure I’d be too intimidated to ask, and too much of a nobody to get an answer if I wasn’t.)  There must be some logic to how a new idea is formed, though it may not be logical in the sense that every new idea is formed with the same logic.  There is probably something personal about the logic we’re using, and it may change as often as the ideas themselves.

This is important because if I want to create a computer program that teaches itself to play chess, for instance, I must obviously create a system in which chess knowledge can be created.  This should not be taken for granted just because we humans can do it without understanding how we do it.

Section 3: Deduction testing of theories

Popper mentions four “lines” of deductive testing:

1. Is the theory internally consistent?  Seems obvious, but complicated theories may imply paradoxes based on internal inconsistencies.

2. What does the theory claim that can be refuted?

3. How does the theory compare with other theories?  Does one explain more than the other?  Is one more refutable than the other?

4. What are the results of our testing of the implications (or predictions) of the theory?  Do they refute our theory?

I think these are all sort of sides of the same coin.  The point is that our theory only gets closer to the truth when it is refuted and corrected.

Section 4: The problem of demarcation

Popper writes on page 11:

The problem of finding a criterion which would enable us to distinguish between the empirical sciences on the one hand, and mathematics and logic as well as ‘metaphysical’ systems on the other, I call the problem of demarcation.

This section was kind of over my head, perhaps because I don’t see how it could be useful for my purposes.  My guess is that he’s trying to ask how we can know whether a theory predicts something that can be tested and refuted, or whether its implications can only ever be intangible.

I was intrigued by what he writes on page 16:

For it cannot be denied that along with metaphysical ideas which have obstructed the advance of science there have been others—such as speculative atomism—which have aided it.  And looking at the matter from the psychological angle, I am inclined to think that scientific discovery is impossible without faith in ideas which are of a purely speculative kind, and sometimes even quite hazy; a faith which is completely unwarranted from the point of view of science, and which, to that extent, is ‘metaphysical’.

I, again, both agree and disagree with Popper here, because he’s not being very specific.  What is “speculative”?  What is “unwarranted”?  I think all ideas a man can have are warranted somehow, even if based on a mistake, a decision to have faith in one thing rather than another.

I would say that scientific discovery is impossible without desire, a person with a goal to understand or achieve some specific thing, which cannot come from the logic of science itself, but contains it and works with it and through it.  That is, logic and science are a means to an end, and do not provide a system with which to create a means to an end.  (Science does not create itself.)

Section 5: Experience as a method

I’m not quite sure what Popper is saying in this section.  My guess is that he’s simply establishing that an experience is what we use as a method to test a theory.

Conclusion

Obviously, I’m not very far into the book yet.  I am very intrigued by it, though quite a bit of it is over my head.  Granted, I’m not trying to understand it for its own sake, but looking for ideas that I can use in my own AI research.  I think Popper tends to go too deeply into subjects I am not as interested in as he discusses the ideas of other philosophers, whereas I am trying to apply all this philosophy to something very concrete: a computer program.

Anyway, I’ll keep reading.